|
comments,
ephemera, speculation, etc.
(protected political
speech and personal opinion)
2022-
2022-06-18 f
FOOD FOR THOUGHT VI
List of Fallacies
A fallacy is reasoning that is
logically invalid, or that undermines the
logical validity of an argument. All
forms of human communication can contain
fallacies.
Because of their
variety, fallacies are challenging to classify. They
can be classified by their structure (formal fallacies) or content (informal fallacies). Informal fallacies,
the larger group, may then be subdivided into
categories such as improper presumption, faulty
generalization, and error in assigning causation and
relevance, among others.
The
use of fallacies is common when the speaker's goal
of achieving common agreement is more important to
them than utilizing sound reasoning. When
fallacies are used, the premise should be
recognized as not well-grounded, the conclusion as
unproven (but not necessarily false), and the
argument as unsound.[1]
[...]
Formal
fallacies
A formal fallacy is
an error in the argument's
form. All formal fallacies
are types of non sequitur.
Propositional
fallacies
A propositional
fallacy is an error that concerns compound
propositions. For a compound proposition to be true,
the truth values of its constituent parts must
satisfy the relevant logical connectives that occur
in it (most commonly: [and], [or], [not], [only if],
[if and only if]). The following fallacies involve
relations whose truth values are not guaranteed and
therefore not guaranteed to yield true conclusions.
Types of propositional fallacies:
Quantification
fallacies
A quantification
fallacy is an error in logic where the quantifiers
of the premises are in contradiction to the
quantifier of the conclusion.
Types of quantification fallacies:
Formal
syllogistic fallacies
Syllogistic fallacies – logical fallacies
that occur in syllogisms.
- Affirmative conclusion from a negative
premise (illicit negative) – a categorical syllogism has a positive
conclusion, but at least one negative premise.
- Fallacy of
exclusive premises – a categorical
syllogism that is invalid because both of its
premises are negative.
- Fallacy of four
terms (quaternio
terminorum) – a categorical syllogism that has four
terms.
- Illicit major – a categorical
syllogism that is invalid because its major term
is not distributed in the major premise
but distributed in the conclusion.
- Illicit minor – a categorical
syllogism that is invalid because its minor term
is not distributed in the minor premise but
distributed in the conclusion.
- Negative conclusion from affirmative
premises (illicit affirmative) – a categorical
syllogism has a negative conclusion but
affirmative premises.
- Fallacy
of the undistributed middle – the middle term in
a categorical syllogism is not distributed.
- Modal fallacy – confusing necessity
with sufficiency. A condition X is necessary for Y
if X is required for even the possibility of Y. X
does not bring about Y by itself, but if there is
no X, there will be no Y. For example, oxygen is
necessary for fire. But one cannot assume that
everywhere there is oxygen, there is fire. A
condition X is sufficient for Y if X, by itself,
is enough to bring about Y. For example, riding
the bus is a sufficient mode of transportation to
get to work. But there are other modes of
transportation – car, taxi, bicycle, walking –
that can be used.
- Modal scope fallacy – a degree of
unwarranted necessity is placed in the conclusion.
Informal
fallacies
Informal fallacies
– arguments that are logically unsound for lack of
well-grounded premises.
- Argument to
moderation (false compromise, middle ground, fallacy
of the mean, argumentum ad temperantiam) – assuming that a
compromise between two positions is always
correct.
- Continuum
fallacy (fallacy of the beard, line-drawing
fallacy, sorites fallacy, fallacy of the heap,
bald man fallacy, decision-point fallacy) –
improperly rejecting a claim for being imprecise.
- Correlative-based
fallacies
- Suppressed
correlative – a correlative
is redefined so that one alternative is made
impossible (e.g., "I'm not fat because I'm
thinner than John.").[17]
- Definist fallacy – defining a term
used in an argument in a biased manner (e.g.,
using "loaded terms"). The person making the
argument expects that the listener will accept the
provided definition, making the argument difficult
to refute.[18]
- Divine
fallacy (argument from incredulity) – arguing
that, because something is so incredible or
amazing, it must be the result of superior,
divine, alien or paranormal agency.[19]
- Double
counting – counting events or occurrences more
than once in probabilistic reasoning, which leads
to the sum of the probabilities of all cases
exceeding unity.
- Equivocation – using a term with
more than one meaning in a statement without
specifying which meaning is intended.
- Ambiguous middle term – using a middle term with multiple
meanings.
- Definitional
retreat – changing the meaning of a word when
an objection is raised. Often paired with
moving the goalposts (see below), as when an
argument is challenged using a common
definition of a term in the argument, and the
arguer presents a different definition of the
term and thereby demands different evidence to
debunk the argument.
- Motte-and-bailey
fallacy – conflating two positions with
similar properties, one modest and easy to
defend (the "motte") and one more
controversial (the "bailey").[23] The arguer first
states the controversial position, but when
challenged, states that they are advancing the
modest position.[24][25]
- Fallacy
of accent – changing the
meaning of a statement by not specifying on
which word emphasis falls.
- Persuasive
definition – purporting to
use the "true" or "commonly accepted" meaning
of a term while, in reality, using an uncommon
or altered definition.
- (cf. the if-by-whiskey
fallacy)
- Ecological fallacy – inferring about the
nature of an entity based solely upon aggregate
statistics collected for the group to which that
entity belongs.
- Etymological
fallacy – assuming that the original or
historical meaning of a word or phrase is
necessarily similar to its actual present-day
usage.
- Fallacy of
composition – assuming that something true of part of
a whole must also be true of the whole.
- Fallacy of division – assuming that
something true of a composite thing must also be
true of all or some of its parts.
- False attribution – appealing to an
irrelevant, unqualified, unidentified, biased or
fabricated source in support of an argument.
- Fallacy of quoting
out of context (contextotomy,
contextomy; quotation mining) – selective
excerpting of words from their original
context to distort the intended meaning.
- False
authority (single authority) – using an expert of
dubious credentials or using only one opinion to
promote a product or idea. Related to the appeal
to authority.
- False dilemma (false dichotomy,
fallacy of bifurcation, black-or-white fallacy) –
two alternative statements are given as the only
possible options when, in reality, there are more.[31]
- False equivalence – describing two or
more statements as virtually equal when they are
not.
- Feedback fallacy – believing in the
objectivity of an evaluation to be used as the
basis for improvement without verifying that the
source of the evaluation is a disinterested party.[32]
- Historian's fallacy – assuming that
decision-makers of the past had identical
information as those subsequently analyzing the
decision. This should not to be
confused with presentism, in which present-day
ideas and perspectives are anachronistically
projected into the past.
- Historical fallacy – believing that
certain results occurred only because a specific
process was performed, though said process may
actually be unrelated to the results.[34]
- Baconian fallacy – supposing that
historians can obtain the "whole truth" via
induction from individual pieces of historical
evidence. The "whole truth" is defined as
learning "something about everything",
"everything about something", or "everything
about everything". In reality, a historian
"can only hope to know something about
something".
- Homunculus
fallacy – using a "middle-man" for explanation;
this sometimes leads to regressive middle-men. It
explains a concept in terms of the concept itself
without explaining its real nature (e.g.:
explaining thought as something produced by a
little thinker – a homunculus – inside the head
simply identifies an intermediary actor and does
not explain the product or process of thinking).
- Inflation of conflict – arguing that, if
experts in a field of knowledge disagree on a
certain point within that field, no conclusion can
be reached or that the legitimacy of that field of
knowledge is questionable.[37][38]
- If-by-whiskey – an argument that
supports both sides of an issue by using terms
that are emotionally sensitive and ambiguous.
- Incomplete
comparison – insufficient information is provided to
make a complete comparison.
- Inconsistent
comparison – different methods of comparison are
used, leaving a false impression of the whole
comparison.
- Intentionality
fallacy – the insistence that the ultimate
meaning of an expression must be consistent with
the intention of the person from whom the
communication originated (e.g. a work of fiction
that is widely received as a blatant allegory must
necessarily not be regarded as such if the author
intended it not to be so).[39]
- Kettle logic – using multiple,
jointly inconsistent arguments to defend a
position.
- Ludic fallacy – failing to take
into account that non-regulated random occurrences
unknown
unknowns can affect the probability of an event
taking place.[40]
- Lump of labour
fallacy – the misconception that there is a fixed
amount of work to be done within an economy, which
can be distributed to create more or fewer jobs.[41]
- McNamara fallacy (quantitative
fallacy) – making an argument using only
quantitative observations (measurements,
statistical or numerical values) and discounting
subjective information that focuses on quality
(traits, features, or relationships).
- Mind projection
fallacy – assuming that a statement about an
object describes an inherent property of the
object, rather than a personal perception.
- Moralistic fallacy – inferring factual
conclusions from evaluative premises in violation
of fact–value
distinction (e.g.: inferring is from ought). Moralistic fallacy
is the inverse of naturalistic
fallacy.
- Moving the
goalposts (raising the bar) – argument in which
evidence presented in response to a specific claim
is dismissed and some other (often greater)
evidence is demanded.
- Nirvana fallacy (perfect-solution
fallacy) – solutions to problems are rejected
because they are not perfect.
- Package deal - treating
essentially dissimilar concepts as though they
were essentially similar.
- Proof by assertion – a proposition is
repeatedly restated regardless of contradiction;
sometimes confused with argument from repetition (argumentum
ad infinitum, argumentum
ad nauseam).
- Prosecutor's
fallacy – a low probability of false matches does
not mean a low probability of some false match being
found.
- Proving too much – an argument that
results in an overly generalized conclusion (e.g.:
arguing that drinking alcohol is bad because in
some instances it has led to spousal or child
abuse).
- Psychologist's
fallacy – an observer presupposes the objectivity
of their own perspective when analyzing a
behavioral event.
- Referential
fallacy[42] – assuming that all
words refer to existing things and that the
meaning of words reside within the things they
refer to, as opposed to words possibly referring
to no real object (e.g.: Pegasus) or that the
meaning comes from how they are used (e.g.:
"nobody" was in the room).
- Reification (concretism,
hypostatization, or the fallacy of misplaced
concreteness) – treating an abstract belief or
hypothetical construct as if it were a concrete,
real event or physical entity (e.g.: saying that
evolution selects which traits are passed on to
future generations; evolution is not a conscious
entity with agency).
- Retrospective
determinism – believing that, because an event has
occurred under some circumstance, the circumstance
must have made the event inevitable (e.g.: because
someone won the lottery while wearing their lucky
socks, wearing those socks made winning the
lottery inevitable).
- Slippery slope (thin edge of the
wedge, camel's
nose)
– asserting that a proposed, relatively small,
first action will inevitably lead to a chain of
related events resulting in a significant and
negative event and, therefore, should not be
permitted.
- Special pleading – the arguer attempts
to cite something as an exemption to a generally
accepted rule or principle without justifying the
exemption (e.g.: a defendant who murdered his
parents asks for leniency because he is now an
orphan).
Improper
premise
- Begging the
question (petitio
principii) – using the
conclusion of the argument in support of itself in
a premise (e.g.: saying that smoking cigarettes is
deadly because cigarettes can kill you; something
that kills is deadly).[44][45]
- Loaded label
– while not inherently fallacious, the use of
evocative terms to support a conclusion is a
type of begging the
question fallacy. When fallaciously used, the
term's connotations are relied on to sway the
argument towards a particular conclusion. For
example, an organic foods advertisement that
says "Organic foods are safe and healthy foods
grown without any pesticides, herbicides, or
other unhealthy additives." Use of the term
"unhealthy additives" is used as support for
the idea that the product is safe.[46]
- Circular reasoning (circulus
in demonstrando) – the reasoner
begins with what he or she is trying to end up
with (e.g.: all bachelors are unmarried males).
- Fallacy of many
questions (complex question, fallacy of
presuppositions, loaded question, plurium
interrogationum) – someone asks a
question that presupposes something that has not
been proven or accepted by all the people
involved. This fallacy is often used rhetorically
so that the question limits direct replies to
those that serve the questioner's agenda. (E.g.,
"Have you or have you not stopped beating your
wife?".)
Faulty
generalizations
Faulty
generalization – reaching a conclusion from weak premises.
- Accident – an exception to a
generalization is ignored.
- No true Scotsman – makes a
generalization true by changing the
generalization to exclude a counterexample.
- Cherry picking (suppressed evidence,
incomplete evidence, argument by half-truth,
fallacy of exclusion, card stacking, slanting) –
using individual cases or data that confirm a
particular position, while ignoring related cases
or data that may contradict that position.[50]
- Nut-picking (suppressed
evidence, incomplete evidence) – using
individual cases or data that falsify a
particular position, while ignoring related
cases or data that may support that position.
- Survivorship bias – a small number
of successes of a given process are actively
promoted while completely ignoring a large
number of failures.
- False
analogy – an argument
by analogy in which the analogy is poorly suited.
- Hasty
generalization (fallacy of
insufficient statistics, fallacy of insufficient
sample, fallacy of the lonely fact, hasty
induction, secundum quid, converse accident, jumping to
conclusions) – basing a broad conclusion on a small
or unrepresentative sample.
- Inductive
fallacy – a more general name for a class of
fallacies, including hasty generalization and its
relatives. A fallacy of induction happens when a
conclusion is drawn from premises that only
lightly support it.
- Misleading
vividness – involves describing an occurrence in
vivid detail, even if it is an exceptional
occurrence, to convince someone that it is more
important; this also relies on the appeal to emotion fallacy.
- Overwhelming
exception – an accurate generalization that comes
with qualifications that eliminate so many cases
that what remains is much less impressive than the
initial statement might have led one to assume.
- Thought-terminating
cliché – a commonly used phrase, sometimes
passing as folk wisdom, used to quell cognitive
dissonance, conceal lack of forethought, move on to
other topics, etc. – but in any case, to end the
debate with a cliché rather than a point.
Questionable
cause
Questionable cause is a general type of
error with many variants. Its primary basis is the
confusion of association with causation, either by
inappropriately deducing (or rejecting) causation or
a broader failure to properly investigate the cause
of an observed effect.
- Cum hoc ergo propter hoc (Latin for "with
this, therefore because of this"; correlation
implies causation; faulty cause/effect,
coincidental correlation, correlation without
causation) – a faulty assumption that, because
there is a correlation between two variables, one
caused the other.
- Post
hoc ergo propter hoc (Latin for "after
this, therefore because of this"; temporal
sequence implies causation) – X happened, then
Y happened; therefore X caused Y.
- Wrong
direction (reverse
causation) – cause and effect are reversed.
The cause is said to be the effect and vice
versa. The consequence
of the phenomenon is claimed to be its root
cause.
- Ignoring a common cause
- Fallacy of
the single cause (causal
oversimplification) – it is assumed that
there is one, simple cause of an outcome when in
reality it may have been caused by a number of
only jointly sufficient causes.
- Furtive fallacy – outcomes are
asserted to have been caused by the malfeasance of
decision makers.
- Gambler's fallacy – the incorrect
belief that separate, independent events can
affect the likelihood of another random event. If
a fair coin lands on heads 10 times in a row, the
belief that it is "due to the number of times it
had previously landed on tails" is incorrect.
- Inverse
gambler's fallacy - the inverse of
the gamblers fallacy. It is the incorrect
belief that on the basis of an unlikely
outcome, the process must have happened many
times before.
- Magical thinking – fallacious
attribution of causal relationships between
actions and events. In anthropology, it refers primarily
to cultural beliefs that ritual, prayer,
sacrifice, and taboos will produce specific
supernatural consequences. In psychology, it refers to an
irrational belief that thoughts by themselves can
affect the world or that thinking something
corresponds with doing it.
- Regression fallacy – ascribes cause
where none exists. The flaw is failing to account
for natural fluctuations. It is frequently a
special kind of post hoc fallacy.
Relevance
fallacies
- Appeal to the stone (argumentum
ad lapidem) – dismissing a claim
as absurd without demonstrating proof for its
absurdity.[59]
- Argument from
ignorance (appeal to ignorance, argumentum ad
ignorantiam) – assuming that a claim is true because
it has not been or cannot be proven false, or vice
versa.
- Argument from
incredulity (appeal to common sense) – "I cannot
imagine how this could be true; therefore, it must
be false."[61]
- Argument from repetition (argumentum
ad nauseam or argumentum
ad infinitum) – repeating an
argument until nobody cares to discuss it any more
and referencing that lack of objection as evidence
of support for the truth of the conclusion;[62][63] sometimes confused
with proof by assertion.
- Argument from
silence (argumentum
ex silentio) – assuming that a
claim is true based on the absence of textual or
spoken evidence from an authoritative source, or
vice versa.[64]
- Ignoratio
elenchi (irrelevant
conclusion, missing the point) – an argument that
may in itself be valid, but does not address the
issue in question.
Red
herring fallacies
A red herring
fallacy, one of the main subtypes of fallacies of
relevance, is an error in logic where a proposition
is, or is intended to be, misleading in order to
make irrelevant or false inferences. This includes
any logical inference based on fake arguments,
intended to replace the lack of real arguments or to
replace implicitly the subject of the discussion.[66][67]
Red herring – introducing a second
argument in response to the first argument that is
irrelevant and draws attention away from the
original topic (e.g.: saying “If you want to
complain about the dishes I leave in the sink, what
about the dirty clothes you leave in the
bathroom?”). In jury trial, it is known as a Chewbacca defense. In political strategy,
it is called a dead cat strategy. See also irrelevant
conclusion.
- Ad hominem – attacking the
arguer instead of the argument. (Note that "ad
hominem" can also refer to the dialectical
strategy of arguing on the basis of the opponent's
own commitments. This type of ad hominem is not a
fallacy.)
- Circumstantial ad
hominem – stating that
the arguer's personal situation or perceived
benefit from advancing a conclusion means that
their conclusion is wrong.[69]
- Poisoning the
well – a subtype of ad
hominem presenting
adverse information about a target person with
the intention of discrediting everything that
the target person says.
- Appeal to motive – dismissing an
idea by questioning the motives of its
proposer.
- Tone policing – focusing on
emotion behind (or resulting from) a message
rather than the message itself as a
discrediting tactic.
- Traitorous critic
fallacy (ergo decedo, 'thus leave') –
a critic's perceived affiliation is portrayed
as the underlying reason for the criticism and
the critic is asked to stay away from the
issue altogether. Easily confused with the association
fallacy ("guilt by association") below.
- Appeal
to authority (argument from authority, argumentum
ad verecundiam) – an assertion is
deemed true because of the position or authority
of the person asserting it.
- Appeal to
accomplishment – an assertion is
deemed true or false based on the
accomplishments of the proposer. This may
often also have elements of appeal to emotion
(see below).
- Courtier's reply – a criticism is
dismissed by claiming that the critic lacks
sufficient knowledge, credentials, or training
to credibly comment on the subject matter.
- Appeal to
consequences (argumentum
ad consequentiam) – the conclusion is
supported by a premise that asserts positive or
negative consequences from some course of action
in an attempt to distract from the initial
discussion.
- Appeal to emotion – manipulating the
emotions of the listener rather than using valid
reasoning to obtain common agreement.
- Appeal to fear – generating
distress, anxiety, cynicism, or prejudice
towards the opponent in an argument.[75]
- Appeal to
flattery – using excessive or insincere praise
to obtain common agreement.
- Appeal to pity (argumentum
ad misericordiam) – generating
feelings of sympathy or mercy in the listener
to obtain common agreement.
- Appeal to
ridicule (reductio ad ridiculum,
reductio ad absurdum, ad absurdum) – mocking or
stating that the opponent's position is
laughable to deflect from the merits of the
opponent's argument. (Note that "reductio ad
absurdum" can also refer to the classic form
of argument that establishes a claim by
showing that the opposite scenario would lead
to absurdity or contradiction. This type of
reductio ad absurdum is not a fallacy.)[78]
- Appeal to spite – generating
bitterness or hostility in the listener toward
an opponent in an argument.[79]
- Judgmental
language – using insulting or pejorative
language in an argument.
- Pooh-pooh – stating that an
opponent's argument is unworthy of
consideration.[80]
- Wishful thinking – arguing for a
course of action by the listener according to
what might be pleasing to imagine rather than
according to evidence or reason.
- Appeal to nature – judgment is based
solely on whether the subject of judgment is
'natural' or 'unnatural'.[82] (Sometimes also
called the "naturalistic fallacy", but is not to
be confused with the other fallacies by that
name.)
- Appeal to novelty (argumentum
novitatis, argumentum
ad antiquitatis) – a proposal is
claimed to be superior or better solely because it
is new or modern. (opposite of appeal to tradition)
- Appeal
to poverty (argumentum
ad Lazarum) – supporting a
conclusion because the arguer is poor (or refuting
because the arguer is wealthy). (Opposite of appeal
to wealth.)
- Appeal to tradition (argumentum
ad antiquitatem) – a conclusion
supported solely because it has long been held to
be true.
- Appeal
to wealth (argumentum
ad crumenam) – supporting a
conclusion because the arguer is wealthy (or
refuting because the arguer is poor). (Sometimes taken
together with the appeal
to poverty as a general appeal to the arguer's
financial situation.)
- Argumentum
ad baculum (appeal to the stick,
appeal to force, appeal to threat) – an argument
made through coercion or threats of force to
support position.
- Argumentum
ad populum (appeal to widespread
belief, bandwagon argument, appeal to the
majority, appeal to the people) – a proposition is
claimed to be true or good solely because a
majority or many people believe it to be so.[88]
- Association fallacy (guilt by association
and honor by association) – arguing that because
two things share (or are implied to share) some
property, they are the same.[89]
- Logic chopping
fallacy (nit-picking, trivial objections) - Focusing on
trivial details of an argument, rather than the
main point of the argumentation.[90][91]
- Ipse dixit (bare assertion
fallacy) – a claim that is presented as true
without support, as self-evidently true, or as
dogmatically true. This fallacy relies on the
implied expertise of the speaker or on an unstated
truism.[92][93]
- Bulverism (psychogenetic
fallacy) – inferring why an argument is being
used, associating it to some psychological reason,
then assuming it is invalid as a result. The
assumption that if the origin of an idea comes
from a biased mind, then the idea itself must also
be a falsehood.[37]
- Chronological
snobbery – a thesis is deemed incorrect because it
was commonly held when something else, known to be
false, was also commonly held.[94][95]
- Fallacy of relative
privation (also known as
"appeal to worse problems" or "not as bad as") –
dismissing an argument or complaint due to what
are perceived to be more important problems. First World problems are a subset of this
fallacy.[96][97]
- Genetic fallacy – a conclusion is
suggested based solely on something or someone's
origin rather than its current meaning or context.
- I'm entitled
to my opinion – a person discredits
any opposition by claiming that they are entitled
to their opinion.
- Moralistic fallacy – inferring factual
conclusions from evaluative premises, in violation
of fact-value distinction; e.g. making
statements about what is, on the basis of claims
about what ought to be. This is the inverse of the
naturalistic fallacy.
- Naturalistic
fallacy – inferring evaluative conclusions from
purely factual premises[100] in violation of fact-value distinction. Naturalistic fallacy
(sometimes confused with appeal to nature) is the inverse of moralistic fallacy.
- Is–ought fallacy – deduce a
conclusion about what ought to be, on the
basis of what is.
- Naturalistic
fallacy fallacy[102] (anti-naturalistic
fallacy)[103] – inferring an
impossibility to infer any instance of ought from is from the general
invalidity of is-ought fallacy, mentioned above. For
instance, is
does imply ought for any proposition , although the naturalistic
fallacy fallacy would falsely declare such an
inference invalid. Naturalistic
fallacy fallacy is a type of argument from
fallacy.
- Straw man fallacy –
misrepresenting an opponent's argument by
broadening or narrowing the scope of a premise
and/or refuting a weaker version of their argument
(e.g.: If someone says that killing animals is
wrong because we are animals too saying "It is not
true that humans have no moral worth" would be a
strawman since they have not asserted that humans
have no moral worth, rather that the moral worth
of animals and humans are equivalent.)
- Texas
sharpshooter fallacy – improperly
asserting a cause to explain a cluster of data.
- Tu quoque ('you too' – appeal
to hypocrisy, whataboutism) – stating that a
position is false, wrong, or should be disregarded
because its proponent fails to act consistently in
accordance with it.
- Two wrongs make a right – assuming that, if
one wrong is committed, another wrong will rectify
it.
- Vacuous truth – a claim that is
technically true but meaningless, in the form no A in B has C, when there is no A in B. For example,
claiming that no mobile phones in the room are on
when there are no mobile phones in the room.
(read
more)
______________________
Permission is hereby granted to any and all to
copy and paste any entry on this page and
convey it electronically along with its URL,
______________________
|
...
News and facts for
those sick and tired of the National Propaganda Radio
version of reality.
- Unlike all the legacy media, our editorial offices are
not in Langley, Virginia.
- You won't catch
us fiddling while Western Civilization burns.
- Close the windows so you don't hear the
mockingbird outside, grab a beer, and see what the hell
is going on as we witness the controlled demolition of
our society.
- The truth
usually comes from one source. It comes quietly, with no
heralds. Untruths come from multiple sources, in unison,
and incessantly.
- The loudest
partisans belong to the smallest parties. The media
exaggerate their size and influence.
|